Advertisement

<i> Vaulting Ambition:</i> Sociobiology and the Quest for Human Nature : by Philip Kitcher (MIT: $25; 447 pp.)

Share
</i>

Philip Kitcher, a bright young British philosopher of science at the University of Minnesota, has written a new book that seeks to thwart an entire discipline. At least where humans are concerned, Kitcher tries to show that the new work in evolutionary biology called “sociobiology” has nothing of value to say and so many misleading and dangerous connotations that it is best restricted to the non-human world.

Sociobiology is the study of the evolution of social interactions within species, and in the last 20 years it has made enormous progress in understanding the principles that underlie social evolution in all species. We now understand clearly that natural selection works on individuals (not groups or species), favoring the individual who leaves the most surviving offspring. We understand, in outline at least, how evolution works with regard to relations among relatives, between the two sexes, and between reciprocal individuals (such as friends) regarding deception, self-deception and much more. One would have thought that scientific progress on such fundamental social issues would inevitably have important implications for our view of ourselves.

Kitcher will have none of it. He grants that natural selection works by accumulating traits that give their bearers high inclusive fitness; that is, high genetic representation in the next generation. He agrees that this process has apparently gone on for nearly 4 billion years here on Earth. Regarding other species, he grants that one useful inference to draw is that this process has by now molded creatures who will act so as to attempt to maximize their inclusive fitness.

Advertisement

Reaching humans, however, he suddenly draws back and says, in effect: Wait! We’ve gone entirely far enough in this line of reasoning, for down this path lie political and behavioral implications that could “stifle the aspirations of millions.” Evaluating human sociobiology, Kitcher adopts special, more rigorous standards and finds the new discipline worse than useless. Its central assumption--that humans, like all other organisms, maximize their own inclusive fitness--he finds “profoundly misguided.” Even were this notion true, he believes we should not study it but should study instead only the underlying mechanisms of life.

Kitcher has taken care to master much of the work that he criticizes. His discussion is often sharp and sophisticated, perhaps the most impressive attack on sociobiology to date. “Vaulting Ambition” is crowded with technical sections describing detailed models for selection acting on social traits. And yet Kitcher’s mastery often seems limited to details and technicalities, as if he wished the central notions of sociobiology to die by neglect rather than counterargument.

He nails one sociobiologist for a careless argument relating kinship theory to human racism, but he neglects William Hamilton’s more careful argument which lines up with a growing body of evidence on kinship recognition and preferential treatment of the genetically similar in both animals and humans. As he prefers peripheral theorists, so also he prefers the periphery of theories. He lavishes an entire chapter on Edmund Wilson’s system for thinking about gene-culture co-evolution, a system of nomenclature and logic that, to say the least, has not been widely adopted.

In Kitcher’s hands, biology is dry and academic. The sights and sounds, the pheromones, the beautiful complexity of ontogeny all disappear from sight, and biology emerges as just another arid, hopelessly flawed system for thinking about the complexities of human existence. Biology may in fact not be of much use in thinking about the complexities of human experience, but it is very useful in thinking about such basics of life as reproduction. Who else should teach us about reproduction: philosophers, social scientists, icon-mongers and holy-write thumpers? Why not biologists?

The proper evaluation of biology, as of any intellectual system, is a cost/benefit analysis; in the case of sociobiology, the costs and benefits of an evolutionary analysis as compared with some other available system of analysis. But Kitcher offers us only a cost analysis and does so without reference to alternatives. That is, he assiduously collects partial errors, possible errors and alleged errors and imagines dire consequences from each. Nowhere does he consider benefits.

Surely sociobiology has corrected errors as well as committed some. Was it not a fundamental advance in both biology and political theory to realize that natural selection does not act for the benefit of the group or the species, as is so commonly supposed, so that we can no longer rationalize (for example) the upper-class adult male’s behavior as being in everyone’s self-interest? Has sociobiology’s concentration on the evolution of altruistic and cooperative behavior not redressed an ancient imbalance within biology according to which the selfish, the aggressive and the narrowly self-serving--”nature red in tooth and claw”--were given undue prominence? Is sociobiology’s emphasis on male parental investment really hostile to the interests of women? And so on.

Advertisement

One final point. The study of natural selection strongly suggests that deception figures in relations between all genetically nonidentical individuals. Selection for such deception has, in turn, generated mechanisms of self-deception, the better to hide the truth from others. In the Western intellectual tradition, philosophy has played a special role in generating and protecting systems of self-deception. Even now, by pretending to rule out entire lines of thought in advance, by attacking methodology, logic and lines of evidence at every turn, philosophy sometimes arrogates to itself a power that may be both deceptive and self-deceptive. The literature of self-deception is growing rapidly within philosophy itself, and it is not to Kitcher’s credit that he draws on it so little.

“Vaulting Ambition” has no internal logic except the purely negative one of creating doubt. No alternative view of human nature emerges from it, no alternative logic or new methodology, nothing positive that we can carry home with us, only errors and alleged errors, arranged in confusing, amusing patterns. Close readers will not be deceived.

Advertisement